By Gordon Hull
Consider the following, too brief summary: following Foucault, one can say that biopolitics is about optimizing populations, or something to that effect. This involves a lot of work on the part of the administrative state, which sets itself up to provide services, everything from sewers and other infrastructure to social safety nets. Different places do this differently, but the goal is to provide for the general welfare. At the same time, as Foucault noted from the get-go (see the last lecture in Society must be Defended), the biopolitical “make live or allow to die” generated a correlative “if you want to live, they must die” (SMD 255). Those Others were excluded from the “population” that the state tried to optimize and so were either allowed to die, or (in cases such as the Nazis) actively killed, or (in the case of American Jim Crow) actively suppressed and marginalized and often killed. These various forms of necropolitics are intimately related as both a matter of historical fact (the Nazis thought Jim Crow an excellent example of race management) and conceptual structure under the rubric of something like state racism. So too, the biopolitics of optimization is historically tied to the necropolitics of state racism, as scholars like Dell McWhorter make clear in the American case, or Agamben does in the case of the German Versuchpersonen.
But biopolitics has more than one variant, or at least so I’ve tried to argue. I think it’s useful to view biopolitics in an earlier phase – what I call “public biopolitics” and a more recent neoliberal version. The two can be distinguished in part by how they conceptualize the members of the population they are trying to benefit, and how they think they might do so. For example, intellectual property on the public model is about public welfare and the benefits to everyone of encouraging inventive activity. On the neoliberal version, the emphasis is much more on individual creators and markets. But the neoliberal version very much embeds a view of public welfare – a society of individual entrepreneurs and consumers, whose well-being is measured by various indicia of consumer welfare.
But what about the necropolitics of neoliberal biopolitics? One obvious avenue to pursue is that those who are excluded from markets are allowed to die. The rhetoric of consumer choice is often then utilized to suggest that they deserve their fate because of a failure to opt-in. Whatever the merits of that avenue, it seems clear enough that more can be said. One component of the U.S. piece is going to be data and surveillance. Biopolitics itself arose in the context of data governance mechanisms like the census, and the importance of data to contemporary capitalism is large and growing. One way the surveillance state implements necropolitics is by what Margaret Hu calls “big data blacklisting:” classifying certain kinds of people as ineligible for many of the things to which other members of the population are entitled (such as employment or the ability to board a commercial aircraft), or rendering them subject to ceremony-free death by drone strike.
In a fascinating recent paper, Michelle Gilman and Rebecca Green offer some important clues to another aspect of the story. Most of the literature about data privacy focuses on what happens when people don’t have enough privacy. Gilman and Green focus on the inverse problem: what happens when people have too much privacy, i.e., when they become invisible in a society predicated on visibility? Working primarily with examples of the undocumented, the homeless, day laborers and those with felony convictions, Gilman and Green tell the story of “populations that remain outside seemingly omnipresent surveillance systems” (257), those who live in the “surveillance gap.” If too much surveillance is bad, so is too little:
Continue reading "The Surveillance Gap and Neoliberal Necropolitics" »
Recent Comments