I posted this on M-Phi yesterday, but now it occurs to me that it might be of interest to some NewAPPS readers as well (the interest sparked by Brit's recent post suggests this much!). It is in fact a review of Stephen Read's edition and translation of Bradwardine's treatise on insolubles, which I just wrote for Speculum.
------------------------------------------------------
Thomas Bradwardine (first half of the 14th
century) is well known for his decisive contributions to physics (he was one of
the founders of the Merton School of Calculators) as well as for his
theological work, in particular his defense of Augustinianism in De Causa Dei. He also led an eventful
life, accompanying Edward III to the battlefield as his confessor, and dying of
the Black Death in 1349 one week after a hasty return to England to take up his
new appointment as the Archbishop of Canterbury.
What is thus far less well known about
Bradwardine is that, prior to these adventures, in the early to mid-1320s, he
worked extensively on logical topics. In this period, he composed his logical tour de force: his treatise on
insolubles. Insolubles were logical puzzles to which Latin medieval authors
devoted a considerable amount of attention (Spade & Read 2009). What is
special about insolubles is that they often involve some kind of self-reference
or self-reflection. The paradigmatic insoluble is what is now known (not a term
used by the medieval authors themselves) as the liar paradox: ‘This sentence is not true’. If it is true, then it
is not true; but if it is not true, then what it says about itself is correct,
namely that it is not true, and thus it is true after all. Hence, we are forced
to conclude that the sentence is both true and false, which violates the principle
of bivalence. It is interesting to note that, in the hands of Tarski, Kripke
and other towering figures, the liar and similar paradoxes re-emerged in the 20th
century as one of the main topics within philosophy of logic and philosophical
logic, and remain to this day a much discussed topic.
Bradwardine’s De insolubilibus has been recently given its first critical
edition, accompanied by an English translation and an extensive introduction,
by Stephen Read. One cannot overestimate the importance of the publication of
this volume for the study of the history of logic as a whole; prior to this
edition, Bradwardine’s text was available in print only in an unreliable edition
by M.L. Roure in 1970. Moreover, Bradwardine’s treatise is arguably the most
important medieval treatise on the topic. So far, the general philosophical
audience is mostly familiar with John Buridan's approach to insolubles;
the relevant passages from chapter 8 of his Sophismata
have received multiple English translations and been extensively discussed. But
Buridan's text pales in comparison to Bradwardine’s treatise; Bradwardine not only
offers a detailed account and refutation of previously held positions (chapters
2 to 5), but he also presents his own novel, revolutionary solution (chapters 6
to 12).
The backbone of Bradwardine’s solution is
the idea that sentences typically signify several things, not only their most
apparent signification. In particular, they signify everything they entail.
Moreover, Bradwardine postulates that, for a sentence to be true, everything it signifies must be the
case; in other words, he associates the notion of truth to universal quantification over what a sentence says. Accordingly, a
sentence is false if at least one of the things it signifies is not the case (existential quantification). He then goes on to prove that insoluble sentences
say of themselves not only that they are not true, but also that they are true.
Hence, such sentences say two contradictory things, which can never both
obtain; so at least one of them is not the case, and thus such sentences are simply
false.
Unlike Buridan, who merely postulates
without further argumentation that every sentence implies that it is true,
Bradwardine makes no such assumption, and instead proves (through a rather
subtle argument, reconstructed in section 5 of Read’s introduction) that
specific sentences, namely insolubles, say of themselves that they are true. In
this sense, Bradwardine’s analysis can rightly be said to be more sophisticated
and compelling than Buridan’s.
Bradwardine’s solution to insolubles is not
only of interest to the historian of logic, and indeed Read and others have
written extensively on its significance for contemporary debates on paradoxes
of self-reference. In fact, a whole volume was published on the philosophical
significance of Bradwardine’s analysis (Rahman et al. 2008). According to Read,
the Bradwardinian framework allows for the treatment of a wide range of
paradoxes as well as for the development of a conceptually motivated,
paradox-resistant theory of truth in terms of quantification over what a
sentence says. Alas, the latter project was not to succeed, for the following
reason. As pointed out by Read himself in his critique of Buridan (Read 2002),
a theory that says that every sentence signifies (implies) its own truth cannot
offer an effective definition of truth, as every sentence becomes what is known
as a truth-teller: one necessary condition for its truth is that be true (as it
is one of the things it says), ensuing a fatal form of circularity. Now, as it
turns out, while Bradwardine does not postulate that every sentence signifies
its own truth, this does follow as a corollary from his general principles
(Dutilh Novaes 2011). Thus, Read’s own criticism against Buridan’s approach
applies to Bradwardine as well. This does not affect the Bradwardine/Read
solutions to the paradoxes because all of them (paradoxes) come out as false, but ultimately
Bradwardine cannot deliver a satisfactory theory of truth.
However, this observation should in no way
be construed as a criticism of Read’s work in general and of his edition and
translation of Bradwardine’s treatise in particular. It is indeed the job of a
reviewer to spot shortcomings in a volume, even if only minor ones, but this
reviewer failed miserably at this endeavor. Read’s volume is an absolutely
exemplary combination of historical and textual rigor (for the edition and translation
of the text) with philosophical insight into the conceptual intricacies of the
material; it is both accessible and sophisticated. As such, it is to be
emphatically recommended to anyone interested in the history of logic as well
as in modern discussions on paradoxes and self-reference.
Recent Comments